Abstract
We present the core support criterion, a voting criterion satisfied by Instant Runoff Voting (IRV) that is analogous to the Condorcet criterion but reflective of a different majority rule philosophy. Condorcet methods can be thought of as conducting elections between each pair of candidates, counting all ballots to determine the winner of each pair-election. IRV can also be thought of as conducting elections between all pairs of candidates but for each pair-election only counting ballots from voters who do not prefer another major candidate (as determined self-consistently from the IRV social ranking) to the two candidates in contention. The appropriateness of including all ballots or a subset of ballots for a pair-election, depends on whether the society deems the entire or a selected ballot set in compliance with freedom of association, which implies freedom of non-association, for a given pair election. Arguments based on freedom of association rely on more information about an electorate than can be learned from ranked ballots alone. We present a freedom-of-association based argument to explain why IRV may be preferable to Condorcet in some circumstances, including the 2022 Alaska special congressional election and the 2009 Burlington Vermont mayoral election, based on the political context of those elections.
Similar content being viewed by others
Explore related subjects
Discover the latest articles and news from researchers in related subjects, suggested using machine learning.Data availability
No datasets were generated or analysed during the current study.
References
Alaska Division of Elections (2022). 2022 General Election – November 8, 2022. https://www.elections.alaska.gov/election-results/e/?id=22genr.
Arrow, K. J. (1963). Social Choice and individual values (2nd ed.). Wiley.
Austen-Smith, D., & Banks, J. (1991). Monotonicity in Electoral systems. American Political Science Review, 85(2), 531–537.
Fishburn, P. C., & Brams, S. J. (1983). Paradoxes of Preferential Voting. Mathematics Magazine, 56(4), 207–214. https://doi.org/10.2307/2689808
Foley, E. B., & Maskin, E. S. (2022, November 1). Alaska’s ranked-choice voting is flawed. But there’s an easy fix. The Washington Posthttps://www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/2022/11/01/alaska-final-four-primary-begich-palin-peltola/.
Gibbard, A. (1973). Manipulation of Voting schemes: A general result. Econometrica, 41(4), 587–601. https://doi.org/10.2307/1914083
Graham-Squire, A. (2022). D. McCune (Ed.), A Mathematical analysis of the 2022 Alaska Special Election for US House. arXiv e-printshttps://doi.org/10.48550/arXiv.2209.04764
Graham-Squire, A., & McCune, D. (2023). An examination of Ranked-Choice Voting in the United States, 2004–2022. Representation. https://doi.org/10.1080/00344893.2023.2221689
Green-Armytage, J. (2011). Four Condorcet-Hare Hybrid Methods for Single-Winner Elections. Voting Matters. Retrieved August 10, 2023, from https://www.votingmatters.org.uk/ISSUE29/I29P1.PDF.
Hill, S. (2022). Alaska election results show why Condorcet is obsolete. DemocracySOS. https://democracysos.substack.com/p/alaska-election-results-show-why.
Ornstein, J. T., & Norman, R. Z. (2014). Frequency of monotonicity failure under Instant Runoff Voting: Estimates based on a spatial model of elections. Public Choice, 161(1/2), 1–9. http://www.jstor.org/stable/24507512.
Otis, D. (2022). Single winner ranked choice voting CVRs, https://doi.org/10.7910/DVN/AMK8PJ, Harvard Dataverse, V9; Burlington_03032009_Mayor.tab.
Satterthwaite, M. A. (1975). Strategy-proofness and Arrow’s conditions: Existence and correspondence theorems for voting procedures and social welfare functions. Journal of Economic Theory, 10(2). https://doi.org/10.1016/0022-0531(75)90050-2
Stephanopoulos, N. (2024). Finding Condorcet. Washington and Lee Law Review, online March 18, 2024. Available at SSRN: https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=4763372.
Tideman, N. (2006). Collective Decisions and Voting: The Potential for Public Choice, Routledge, ISBN 9780754647171.
Woodall, D. R. (1997). Monotonicity of single-seat preferential election rules. Discrete Applied Mathematics, 77(1). https://doi.org/10.1016/S0166-218X(96)00100-X. ISSN 0166-218X.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Contributions
All authors whose names appear on the submission made substantial contributions to the conception of the work drafted the work or revised it critically for important intellectual content; approved the version to be published; and agree to be accountable for all aspects of the work in ensuring that questions related to the accuracy or integrity of any part of the work are appropriately investigated and resolved.
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Competing interests
The authors declare no competing interests.
Additional information
Publisher’s Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.
About this article
Cite this article
Hyman, R., Otis, D., Allen, S. et al. A majority rule philosophy for instant runoff voting. Const Polit Econ 35, 425–436 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-024-09442-3
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-024-09442-3