Abstract
A voting rule is monotonic if a winning candidate never becomes a loser by being raised in voters’ rankings of candidates, ceteris paribus. Plurality with a runoff is known to fail monotonicity. To see how widespread this failure is, we focus on French presidential elections since 1965. We identify mathematical conditions that allow a logically conceivable scenario of vote shifts between candidates that may lead to a monotonicity violation. We show that eight among the ten elections held since 1965 (those in 1965 and 1974 being the exceptions) exhibit this theoretical vulnerability. To be sure, the conceived scenario of vote shifts that enables a monotonicity violation may not be plausible under the political context of the considered election. Thus, we analyze the political landscape of these eight elections and argue that for two of them (2002 and 2007 elections), the monotonicity violation scenario was plausible within the conjuncture of the time.
Similar content being viewed by others
Explore related subjects
Discover the latest articles and news from researchers in related subjects, suggested using machine learning.Notes
Black (1958) and Brams and Fishburn (2002) give a comprehensive account of this condition, which should be distinguished from other stronger monotonicity conditions that are more oriented to the implementability of collective choice rules. For those different monotonicities of implementation theory, once can see Maskin and Sjöström (2002).
Felsenthal and Nurmi (2017) present a detailed account of monotonicity failures.
See Doron and Kronick (1977) for arguments against using non-monotonic voting rules.
Golder (2005) discusses the use of PwR in different elections around the world.
The qualification “restricted” implicitly assumes that voters’ preferences do not change between the two rounds and that strategic voting is not a concern. See Conitzer and Sandholm (2005) for a formalization of PwR as a protocol.
Under this adaptation that overlooks preferences, the question on whether voters’ preferences change between the two rounds vanish. In a similar vein, strategic voting is not a concern. See Footnote 5.
Although we postpone the discussion on the runoff outcome to the next section where we use real election data, we note right away that the condition “\({C}_{1}\) not exceeding the threshold of 50 votes” ensures that \({C}_{1}\) does not become the PwR winner without needing a runoff.
on that particularly prevails when the elec.
Although in French politics candidates typically stand out more than the party they are associated with, to be more informative to a larger audience, we gave the party names in the tables and used their English translations.
Although the inequality in Proposition 1 requires \(x\) < 30.06, the actual vote of Chirac which is 19.94 is the binding upper bound on \(x\). This issue applies to the 1995, 2002 and 2017 elections as well.
Some changes may be more unlikely than others but for the purpose of our analysis a single category that reflects unlikeliness suffices.
Among the reasons for such a shift was the steady move of Christian west towards left and the popularity of socialism among youngsters who vote for the first time in 1981.
At the end of our analysis, we are able to qualify the 2002 election as one which is practically open to an upward 1.1 monotonicity violation.Thus, we do not analyze the plausibility of other 1.k violation scenarios for k > 1.
psos.com/sites/default/files/files-fr-fr/doc_associe/rapport_vague13.pdf.
We thank an anonymous referee for suggesting this perspective.
A well-known instance of manipulative vote transfers under non-monotonic voting rules is the referendum in Italy held on 12 June 2005 under the (non-monotonic) majority with quorum rule, where the Catholic Church, being against the withdrawal of a law dealing with medically assisted procreation, asked its supporters to abstain rather than casting a negative vote (Houy (2009)).
References
Black D (1958) The Theory of Committees and Elections. Springer, New York
Bradley P (1995) STV and monotonicity: a hands-on assessment. Representation 33(2):46–47
Brams SJ, Fishburn PC (2002) Voting procedures. In: Arrow JK, Sen AK, Suzumura K (eds) Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 173–236
Conitzer V, Sandholm T (2005) Communication complexity of common voting rules. In: Proceedings of the 6th ACM Conference on Electronic Commerce, 78–87
Criddle B, Bell DS (1981) The 1981 French elections: the victory of the left. The World Today 37(7/8):282–292
Doron G, Kronick R (1977) Single transferable vote: an example of perverse social choice function. Am J Polit Sci 21:303–311
Durand C, Blais A, Larochelle M (2004) The polls in the 2002 French presidential election: an autopsy. Public Opin Q 68(4):602–622
Felsenthal DS, Nurmi H (2017) Monotonicity failures afflicting procedures for electing a single candidate. Springer, Switzerland
Frears J (1988) The 1988 French presidential election. Gov Oppos 23(3):276–289
Golder M (2005) Democratic electoral systems around the world, 1946–2000. Elect Stud 24:103–121
Graham-Squire A, Zayatz N (2020) Lack of monotonicity anomalies in empirical data of Instant Runoff elections. Representation. https://doi.org/10.1080/00344893.2020.1785536
Houy NA (2009) Characterization of majority voting rules with quorums. Theor Decis 67:295–301
Keskin U, Sanver MR, Tosunlu HB (2020) Recovering non-monotonicity problems of voting rules. Social Choice and Welfare. Forthcoming
Lepelley D, Chantreuil F, Berg S (1996) The likelihood of monotonicity paradoxes in run-off elections. Math Soc Sci 31(3):133–146
Maskin E, Sjöström T (2002) Implementation theory. Handb Soc Choice Welf 1:237–288
Miller NR (2017) Closeness matters: monotonicity failure in IRV elections with three candidates. Public Choice 173(1–2):91–108
Muller E, Satterthwaite MA (1977) The equivalence of strong positive association and strategy-proofness. J Econ Theory 14(2):412–418
Ornstein JT, Norman RZ (2014) Frequency of monotonicity failure under Instant Runoff Voting: estimates based on a spatial model of elections. Public Choice 161(1–2):1–9
Penniman H (1969) French elections, 1969. World Affairs 132(2):101–117
Quas A (2004) Anomalous outcomes in preferential voting. Stochastics Dyn 04(1):95–105
Sauger N (2007) The French legislative and presidential elections of 2007. West Eur Polit 30(5):1166–1175
Smith JH (1973) Aggregation of preferences with variable electorate. Econometrica 41(6):1027–1041
Van der Straeten K, Laslier JF, Blais A (2013) Vote au pluriel: how people vote when offered to vote under different rules. Polit Sci Polit 46(2):324–328
Acknowledgements
We thank Denis Bouyssou, Olivier Cailloux, Uğur Özdemir and Jérôme Lang for their precious comments on earlier version of this paper; Jean Lainé, Jean-François Laslier, Vincent Merlin and Ali Özkes for very useful discussions; an anonymous referee and an anonymous associate editor for their thoughtful reviews that improved our work. This paper is a part of ‘Polarization viewed from a social choice perspective’ (POSOP) research project that is carried on under the RDI program funded by İstanbul Bilgi University. We would like to thank POSOP for the support.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Keskin, U., Sanver, M.R. & Tosunlu, H.B. Monotonicity violations under plurality with a runoff: the case of French presidential elections. Soc Choice Welf 59, 305–333 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-022-01397-4
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-022-01397-4